next up previous
Next: Conclusions Up: Towards an Information-Neutral Previous: Strategy Aggregation

Assessing the Role of Uncertainty in Declared-Strategy Voting

Having sketched the framework for a declared-strategy voting system, we will now describe three ways of assembling the components, each of which results in a system with different properties. The main difference between these systems lies in the way we account for uncertainty. We will explain each system and show the outcome each would produce given an example set of voter preference information.

In our example election, we will assume for simplicity that no voters are indifferent between any pair of candidates; thus we need not consider tie-breaking rules. The utility vectors for our voters are as follows:

Our first system relies on random methods for calculation uncertainty. In this system voters submit their preference information and tie-breaking strategies without knowing the uncertainty factor that will be used. Just prior to the evaluation phase, a random uncertainty factor is calculated. The ballots are then evaluated using the batch technique and the random uncertainty value. This procedure results in a system that elicits sincere preference information from most voters. The only voters for whom it is not necessarily rationally optimal to submit sincere preference information are those who have found a probabilistic sophisticated strategy (this would require prior knowledge of the preferences of the other voters). Because such a strategy is not likely to be found by many voters, this system is highly resistant to manipulation. However, it is also unstable, as the results may vary depending on the random uncertainty value chosen.

For example, with a random uncertainty factor of .027, the evaluation would proceed as follows:

  1. Calculate an initial predicted outcome point by evaluating the equation for each voter using equal pivot probabilities. This will result in a predicted outcome point which assumes that all voters will vote sincerely. In this case that point occurs at (.48, .24, .28).

  2. Use the predicted outcome point and the uncertainty factor of .027 to calculate first-round pivot probabilities according to Hoffman's method. In this case the pivot probabilities are found to be: , , and .

  3. Evaluate the equation for each voter using the new pivot probabilities and calculate a new predicted outcome point. In this example, the F and H voters will select insincere strategies while all the other voters will select sincere strategies. The new predicted outcome point will occur at (.62, .12, .26).

  4. Use the first-round predicted outcome point and the uncertainty factor of .027 to calculate second-round pivot probabilities.

  5. Evaluate the equations for each voter again, this time using the second-round pivot probabilities. In this round, the E voters join the F and H voters in selecting insincere strategies. The second-round predicted outcome point is (.62, 0, .38).

  6. Use the second-round predicted outcome point and the uncertainty factor of .027 to calculate third-round pivot probabilities.

  7. Evaluate the equations for each voter again, this time using the third-round pivot probabilities. In this round the H voters return to their sincere strategies, resulting in a third-round predicted outcome point of (.48, 0, .52).

  8. Repeating the process for subsequent rounds reveals that the third-round predicted outcome point is an equilibrium outcome.

Depending on the random uncertainty factor selected in this example, equilibrium outcomes may occur at (.48, 0, .52), (.72, .24, 0), or (.62, .24, .14). Voters wishing to use a sophisticated strategy may do so by selecting insincere utilities which will result in a possible outcome set more favorable to their preferred candidates. But unless they can find a sophisticated strategy that will produce the same outcome regardless of the uncertainty factor used, the sophisticated strategy will not always result in the desired outcome. For example, if all voters submit sincere strategies here, candidate 1 will win whenever . A and B voters might select a sophisticated strategy in which they would submit the utility vector (9, 10, 0). This would result in a victory for 1 if . Thus, depending on the range of possible random values, voters may be able to increase their chances of achieving a preferred outcome by voting insincerely, but they can rarely guarantee a preferred outcome this way. In addition, by voting insincerely, voters lose their opportunity to make their true preferences known.

Our second system is similar to the first; however, it involves repeating the evaluation process many times, using different uncertainty values for each repetition. The uncertainty values would be selected so as to find all possible outcomes for the set of voter preferences submitted. This system is also highly resistant to manipulation. However, it suffers from being indecisive; this system selects a set of outcomes rather than a single outcome.

Returning to our example, if all voters submit sincere utility vectors, the outcome set will contain the possible outcomes listed above: (.48, 0, .52), (.72, .24, 0), and (.62, .24, .14). This outcome set selects either candidate 1 or candidate 3 as the winner. Voters who submit insincere utility vectors may be able to shift the outcome points or increase or decrease the number of points in the outcome set. In this case, if A and B voters submitted the utility vector (9, 10, 0), the outcome space would contain the points: (.60, .40, 0) (.32, .40, .28). This outcome set selects either candidate 1 or candidate 2 as the winner. Thus supporters of candidate 1 are still not able to remove outcome points which select other candidates from the outcome set. Depending on what procedures are used to further narrow the outcome set, they may have advantaged or disadvantaged candidate 1 by voting insincerely.

Our final system uses a known arbitrary uncertainty value (or alternately an uncertainty value based on voter preferences --- this would be computable by anyone who is able to obtain voter preference information prior to the election). This system is both stable and decisive. The only voters for whom it is not necessarily rationally optimal to submit sincere preference information are those who have found a sophisticated strategy. Thus the system resists manipulation (although not as well as the other two systems).

Once again, our example shows that each of three possible outcomes is possible depending on the uncertainty value used. Because voters know the uncertainty value in advance, they may formulate sophisticated strategies in which is a constant. (Even if we select based on some aggregation of voter preference information, voters with prior information about the presences of others could deduce this number in advance. Likewise if voters submitted individual risk factors to be used for , some voters may be able to obtain this information in advance; however, such an approach is likely to further complicate the process of formulating a sophisticated strategy and thus reduce the number of voters who do so successfully.) So, if was selected to be .01, candidate 3 would win if all voters vote sincerely. A and B voters might be tempted to use a sophisticated strategy and submit the insincere utility vector (9, 10, 0). This would result in a victory for candidate 1. However, anticipating that A and B voters will use a sophisticated strategy, E and F voters would also use a sophisticated strategy and submit the insincere utility vector (0, 9, 10). This would result in a victory for candidate 3. In this example, voters cannot change the winner by using a sophisticated strategy (assuming all voters who could benefit from using a sophisticated strategy act accordingly); however, this is not always the case.



next up previous
Next: Conclusions Up: Towards an Information-Neutral Previous: Strategy Aggregation



Lorrie Faith Cranor
Thu Apr 25 14:31:14 CDT 1996